A fossil of Tiktaalik, one of the most
famous examples of the transition between lobe-finned fish and
four-legged animals, was found in the Canadian arctic in 2004.
Photograph by Eduard SolĂ . Used unde the Creative Commons
Attribution-Share
Alike 3.0 Unported license.
|
The
fossil evidence appears to support evolutionary theory. Different
species appear in the record in exactly the order one would expect if
descent with modification were true.
But
what if that seemingly obvious evidence was, in fact, a clever ruse?
This is one argument
put forth by certain creationists, who believe the Earth was brought
into being by a god who made life appear via some supernatural means
alluded to in the Bible (or one of several other sacred religious
texts). For these people, the fossil record evidence is merely
another test of faith.
This
proposal, often dismissed out of hand by scientists and rarely
brought to its logical conclusion by those who espouse it,
nevertheless is consistent with a particular metaphysically-derived
epistemological argument that has been advocated by serious
philosophers, including none other than Rene Descartes.
To
understand the Cartesian metaphysical-epistemological framework, it
is useful first to understand two other such frameworks from which
different conclusions about the meaning of the fossil record can be
drawn. Bertrand Russell and Galileo Galilei are illustrious
representatives of these alternative camps.
Russell
is a metaphysical
naturalist (sometimes also called ontological naturalism). That
is, he believes that both the means of discovering knowledge
(epistemology) and the nature of the universe (metaphysics) are built
on a material foundation. This is the de facto position of science,
which does does not permit supernatural explanations.
Russell,
in chapter V of his “Problems
in Philosophy,” posits that all knowledge is derived
from sensory-mediated perception of the physical world – what he
calls “acquaintance.” This acquaintance accounts not only for all
we can call truth; it is the very substrate on which all statements
of any kind depend. We cannot even have language without this direct
experience known as acquaintance: “Every proposition which we
can understand must be composed wholly of constituents with which we
are acquainted [Emphasis in original].”
Russell’s
epistemology comes from a metaphysical position in which there is no
room for faith, for faith is that in which one believes without being
able to experience it. To him, the only reason a creationist could
even propose the fossil record ruse is because of experience of the
actual fossil record accompanied by past experiences of lies he had
encountered. The notion of a god, far from being some transcendental
true being, is merely a composite of experienced human attributes
transferred to an imagined deity.
Galileo
would likely agree with Russell that the fossil evidence supports
evolution, for Galileo is a methodological naturalist. But their
agreement would end where metaphysics begins. Although Galileo
believes that the proper way of gaining knowledge about the world
around us is by looking at material reality, he also maintains that
the nature of the universe comprises more than the material;
specifically, he believes the soul, the Catholic God, and other such
Biblical notions are equally - if not in a superior sense - true.
Galileo
draws this distinction between the realm of science and the realm of
the soul in his “Letter
to the Grand Duchess Christina of Tuscany.” In the letter,
Galileo attempts to show that one cannot take all passages in the
Bible literally. He does not go as far as to say that the Bible is
discordant with nature. Indeed, he thinks the Bible justifies the
natural order of the world. However, he argues that new discoveries
may lead to new interpretations of some verses, and that others which
do not directly bear on matters of salvation may in fact be
purposefully skewed so as to be understandable to the masses, even if
the information is not, strictly speaking, accurate.
The
distinction Galileo makes between nature and the heavenly is key to
his conciliatory position. “I should judge,” he writes, “that
the authority of the Bible was designed to persuade men of those
articles and propositions which, surpassing all human reasoning could
not be made credible by science, or by any other means than through
the very mouth of the Holy Spirit.”
Here
Galileo diverges from Russell, whose metaphysics do not admit of a
means for obtaining knowledge outside that which is accessible to
science and reasoning.
Galileo's
methodological naturalism is perhaps the most popular of the three
frameworks today. Most people accept the authority of the
understanding that the scientific endeavor produces about the physical
world, while continuing to believe in a realm of life after death
that is separate and inscrutable from this side of the mortal veil.
His argument, in fact, reflects the current official position of the
Roman Catholic Church that once persecuted him.
Methodological
naturalism is the de jure position of science, because while science
does not permit the supernatural, it also does not refute the
supernatural.
Methodological
naturalism does, however, face some significant challenges. The
instability it introduces into interpretations of sacred texts can
(despite Galileo's assertions to the contrary) lead to questions
about the soul, the nature of gods, and salvation. More importantly,
though, as science has expanded into territories previously in the
purview of scripture, the unknowable space open to the spiritual has
shrunken. Increasingly this framework takes on a “god of the gaps”
quality.
Descartes,
in contrast with the other frameworks, rejects naturalism altogether.
As a devout Christian, he cannot accept the metaphysical version, and
as a sophisticated thinker he recognizes the incompleteness of the
methodological version.
Descartes'
method is quite ingenious. Rather than asserting belief based on
evidence of any sort, he instead embraces an extreme form of doubt of
which even the ancient Greek Skeptics would be envious. For
Descartes, this extreme doubt allows him to withdraw from the natural
world; he does not plan to seek confirmation of the supernatural
there.
By
avoiding material objects, Descartes can assert only that which he
finds in his own mind, which he takes to be the starting point of
“true” reality, making him an idealist in the Platonic sense. A
few ideas, he decides after establishing that his mind must exist,
have more certainty than empirical observations. One of these ideas
is perfection, which he declares is the essence of God. Thus he
writes in the synopsis
of his "Meditations”
that “the idea of being perfect, which is found in our minds,
possesses so much objective reality...that it must be held to arise
from a cause absolutely perfect.”
Descartes'
doubtful idealism offers powerful support for the creationist
argument of false evidence. His method cannot be waved away on
account of the evidence precisely because the evidence is not
considered a reliable source for knowledge claims. It admits no
assault from the empirical world.
There
are, of course, weaknesses to Descartes' approach. One is that he
must arrive at the concept of self prior to establishing the concept
of God. He also chooses the categories on which he will focus in an
explicit effort to arrive at God: for instance, he assumes
definitional relations in making doubt synonymous with imperfection
and imperfection antonymous with perfection. Perfection is neither
objective nor specific, nor is it necessarily the same as “good.”
One can be perfectly evil. Russell would likely counter Descartes by
pointing out that these definitions and relations are formed in the
first place on the knowledge of acquaintance, thus undermining the
very effort Descartes had made in escaping sensory information.
A
second concern for Descartes' method is that it tells us nothing in
particular about God, beyond it being a form of absolute perfection.
It certainly does not give credence to any particular scripture or
deity, as Galileo's framework does.
Once
accepted, though, the Cartesian God works in creationists' favor in
that it offers assurance that a God does exist, and that that God is
more “real” than any physical object, including fossil evidence.
Assured of the prevailing truth of God, one is free to adopt any
faith tradition one prefers and to reject any countervailing evidence
as merely a test of that more well-established faith.
The
differences between the metaphysical-epistemological frameworks
epitomized by Descartes, Russell, and Galileo are today playing out
in the heated debates about the veracity of evolutionary theory. Each
has subtle, but practical, consequences for major societal issues,
from religious adherence to education policy. Understanding them is
crucial to understanding the textures of these defining public and
personal debates.